いい気分だわ!

Why Hoppe is still a neo-Marxist (and why Hoppeanism is a kind of collectivist anarchism)

Hans-Hermann Hoppe is often portrayed as a radical individualist and a staunch advocate of anarcho-capitalism. His foundational work in argumentation ethics and his rigorous critique of democracy seem to place him firmly within the Rothbardian tradition. However, beneath this libertarian veneer lies a paradox: Hoppe’s political model bears a striking resemblance to collectivist anarchism and exhibits intellectual underpinnings akin to Neo-Marxism.

1. Frankfurt Roots, Libertarian Ends

Hoppe’s academic journey began at the University of Frankfurt, where he studied under Jürgen Habermas, a leading figure of the Frankfurt School. Immersed in discourse ethics and critical rationalism, Hoppe was influenced by the methodological frameworks of critical theory. Although he later rejected the egalitarian and socialist conclusions of the Frankfurt School, the dialectical methods he absorbed remained integral to his work.

His theory of argumentation ethics—a purported a priori justification for libertarian property norms—is essentially a reworking of Habermas’s discourse ethics. This ironic inheritance reveals that Hoppe critiques leftist egalitarianism using tools forged in the same philosophical furnace. He turns their tools against their conclusions, but the tools remain.

2. The Collectivist Logic of “Covenant Communities”

In his vision of a stateless society, Hoppe proposes the establishment of gated, culturally homogeneous “covenant communities.” These private-property-based enclaves enforce strict entry rules, permitting only those who conform to the moral and cultural norms of the community. Individuals can be excluded not for violating others’ rights, but for deviating from shared customs—be it political beliefs, sexual orientation, or lifestyle choices.

This vision contradicts individualist anarchism at a fundamental level. Classical individualist anarchist thought—from Stirner to Tucker—emphasizes voluntary association, tolerance of diverse beliefs, and the primacy of personal sovereignty. Hoppe’s model, by contrast, elevates collective moral order over individual liberty, effectively subordinating the person to the community.

In practice, Hoppean anarchism requires conformity to traditional norms, enforced not by the state, but by social exclusion and internalized shame. These are tools of communal pressure, not expressions of radical autonomy.

3. Hoppean Order vs. Real-World Complexity

Hoppeans argue that so-called “degenerate” behaviors—pornography, drug use, gender nonconformity, sexual liberalism—are destroying society. They’re not entirely wrong, but they’re not entirely right either. If we examine the world’s wealthiest and most stable nations by GDP, we observe a paradox: many of them embody a messy balance between traditionalism and permissiveness.

GDP encompasses everything from sex toys, porn, and recreational drugs to loud music festivals and niche subcultures. Yet many of these same countries still retain strong cultural cohesion, family structures, or religious traditions in parts of society. They’re not bastions of biblical morality, but they’re not moral wastelands either.

Hoppe’s vision of order assumes that peace and prosperity depend on absolute moral uniformity. However, in reality, the market thrives in pluralistic, even contradictory environments. Economic health and civilizational stability do not require purging every subversive impulse—they require tolerating contradiction. The Hoppean impulse is to tidy up human life into ideological consistency. History suggests that human flourishing is more chaotic than Hoppe would admit.

4. Michéa and the Conservative Trap

French philosopher Jean-Claude Michéa offers an important insight here. While conservatives like Hoppe rail against “degeneracy,” they fail to confront its true engine: the market economy itself. Capitalism, especially in its liberal and consumerist form, thrives on endless disruption, novelty, and transgression. The market doesn’t just tolerate fringe behaviors—it commodifies and promotes them. From pornography to hyper-individualistic identity niches, capitalism profits by turning rebellion into branding.

Michéa argues that the only consistent path to a society rooted in shared moral norms is the abolition of the market. True moral coherence—not the performative moralism of gated communities—requires removing the economic structures that reward destabilization and decadence. In this sense, it is not conservatism, but a form of communism or post-market socialism, that can provide the conditions for a society to align cultural values with material incentives. Conservatives like Hoppe desire the outcomes of communitarian life while preserving the system that erodes it.

A stark, if extreme, example is North Korea. Despite being widely condemned on other grounds, it offers a clear illustration of a society fighting “degeneracy” through communism. There, the state has entirely suppressed the consumer market, along with the liberal cultural expressions that accompany it. The result is a hyper-conservative society—rigid, moralistic, and explicitly anti-liberal—achieved not through capitalism or voluntary association, but through total market abolition. While few would endorse North Korea as a desirable model, its existence proves the point: if one wants to eliminate degeneracy, communism—not free markets—does it more effectively.

5. Echoes of Collectivist Anarchism

Hoppe’s “covenant communities” resemble the federated, self-managed communes favored by collectivist anarchists such as Bakunin. While his economics remain capitalist, the moral gatekeeping he advocates mirrors the logic of collectivist anarchism: group-defined values shape membership and behavior.

In contrast, figures like Samuel Edward Konkin III—another Rothbardian offshoot—explicitly rejected all forms of communitarianism. Konkin envisioned a decentralized network of self-employed individuals, where ideology was irrelevant so long as interactions remained voluntary. He opposed wage labor not from a Marxist stance, but because it created dependency and hierarchy—two enemies of autonomy.

Hoppe’s model, however, is inward-looking, traditionalist, and exclusionary. His anarchism seeks not just the absence of the state, but the enforcement of moral coherence. In this, he more closely resembles a conservative collectivist than a radical individualist.

6. The Reactionary Paradox

Ironically, Hoppe’s effort to resist Marxism ends up mimicking it. His emphasis on collective norms, communal identity, and ideological uniformity reflects the very structures he claims to oppose. He inverts the content—replacing progress with tradition—but preserves the collectivist form.

This is a common trap for reactionaries. In their battle against modernity, they often find themselves recreating its structure, just with different aesthetics. Hoppe’s traditionalism, though stateless, still operates like a moral code to be imposed.

Conclusion: The Right-Wing Neo-Marxist

Despite his branding, Hoppe’s anarchism is not rooted in individual liberty. It is built on collective identity, moral exclusion, and social control. While his model claims to be voluntarist and market-based, it amounts to a gated community of ideological sameness. His anarchism is not egoist, not pluralist, and certainly not tolerant.

If we must categorize him, Hoppe is not the individualist mirror of left-anarchism. He is its reactionary reflection—a collectivist anarchist with property titles and dress codes. A defender of order, yes—but not of freedom.


One response to “Why Hoppe is still a neo-Marxist (and why Hoppeanism is a kind of collectivist anarchism)”

  1. It’s really a cool and helpful piece of info. I’m happy that you shared this useful information with us.

    Please stay us informed like this. Thanks for sharing.

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *